In Order to Receive Notifications of New Blogs, Click The Like Button Find us on Google+

Friday, November 15, 2013

Bankrupt Cities

Here are some quick Friday thoughts on ethical issues of bankrupt cities:

There seem to be two main issues: How to work out who gets what monies from the city (similar to the issues of a company going bankrupt) and which if any assets the city has the right to retain.  

Here are my 4 thoughts - just initial thoughts:

1. First discussion (of two) of debtor's obligation:

According to Mishna Arakhin  6:3-4, a debtor retains the right to basic necessities of survival (a roof and bed etc) and of generating income (tools of his trade if he must own his own in order to work).

Based on this model, what if anything does the right of retaining basic necessities mean for a group of people (as in a city)?

We have m. Megilla's references that a sefer Torah and a beit knesset are basic.  Does that mean even in the face of debt?  Actually, we have a history of Halakha of defaulting communities (Vaad ha-Kehilot of Poland and Lithuania; some famous kupot/kollelim of Yerushalayim).  I have never looked into the Halakhic rulings but I recall that some exist.


2. As regards multiple creditors and Detroit, how should limited money of default be divided fairly?

a. One angle on the issue is to view everyone owed money as in the same mess and ask what to do now.  Do we (society) wish to divide the money equally [obviously no more to anybody than he is actually owed] so that each party gets minimally the same amount to help them survive and move on in life from this point forward?  OR do we wish to divide the losses proportionately since each party had made decisions/set up their life in reliance on future repayment of a certain sum of money and so each party's damage depends on the proportion lost?

The matter is debated in Halakhic history. 

a-1. First, let's see how m. Ketubot 10:4 plays it out.  In this mishna one person is owed 100, another 200, and a third is owed 300.  In this case, the two concerns are balanced:

      מי שהיה נשוי שלש נשים ומת 
כתובתה של זו מנה ושל זו מאתים ושל זו שלש מאות 
ואין שם אלא מנה - חולקין בשוה
   (75 =) היו שם מאתים - של מנה נוטלת חמשים, של מאתים ושל שלש מאות שלשה שלשה של זהב 
  (150 =)היו שם שלש מאות - של מנה נוטלת חמשים ושל מאתים מנה ושל שלש מאות ששה של זהב 
וכן ג' שהטילו לכיס פיחתו או הותירו כך הן חולקין:

First case: everyone gets the same amount - 33.3 + 33.3 + 33.3 - and the losses are very disproportional.  The concern seems to be that everyone has an equal right to receive the same share of the sum needed to move forward in life.  Losses are ignored.

Second case: The smallest sum creditor gets half of his money with the others also getting the same sum and more.  The others then divide the difference equally. 50/100, 50+25, and 50+25.  The concern seems to be to balance between granting everyone the same sum but only up to half of the debt.   Anything beyond half goes to the parties that are owed more money

Third case: Everyone get the ideal (in this type of case) - half of the money that they were owed: 50/100, 100/200, 150/300.

a-2. The Geonim, however, say that everyone gets their proportion (referenced in Rambam malveh ve-loveh 20:10).
For those who prefer concrete numbers:
If only 100 were available, it would be approximately: 16+/100, 32+/200, 48+/300.

a-3. Rambam says that the money is divided so that each smaller party gets as much as up to their whole debt and not just half - and only then is the rest divided equally (malveh ve-loveh 20:7).  The position codified in the Rambam prioritized giving everybody equal footing to move forward [obviously not beyond the money a party was owed]

For those who prefer concrete numbers:

If only 100 were available: 33.3/100 + 33.3/200 + 33.3/300

If 300 were available: 100/100 + 100/200 + 100/300

If 400 were available: 100/100 + 150/200 + 150/300

If 500 were available: 100/100 + 200/200 + 200/300

b.  A problem with this analysis, however, is that although it can express values and is great for the classroom, it seems to ignore the intuition of greater damage to workers than to banks.  It is true that big lenders need to be appeased so that they will lend to and service cities in the future (she-lo tin'ol delet), but we seem to be missing an attempt to balance that and the workers' more severe need.  Anybody who has actually done business will realize, however, that it is also possible that a contractor and his employees or heavy bond holders etc will go under due to the canceled debt.

So let us clarify what underlies that intuition if it does make sense.  The intuition that workers deserve money more than the banks deserve the money seems to come from two related considerations:  Banks tend to evaluate their risks well, and banks can absorb the loss.

Although this is not always true (Enron etc etc), one basic reason that it seems to be true is because banks banks try to protect their loans.  So, we possibly should distinguish between liens (which also facilitate loans - she-lo tin'ol delet) and other monies owed.  In Halakha: when it comes to liens, first creditors collect first on the assumption that later creditors knew that they had less powerful liens. Notice that this is not an issue of the mess of debts owed later but of acquiring rights/guarantees at the time of the initial loan.  According to this reasoning, banks have the upper hand as regards mortgaged but not as regards unprotected debt.

c. That is still problematic, however, because we have not discussed who we think deserves the money:

A libertarian will say that workers overdrew on the city's resources and brought about their own ruin.  A liberal will say that the banks cooperated with the city's rich (and the suburbians) to drain the city and brought about the end of their own party.

A non-ideological analysis, however, would more simply recognize that each side's responsibility grew as the situation worsened:  
1. Imagine that I am a worker who fights for a more pay while facing a rich city. No reason to avoid that.  Imagine that I am a bank lending to a rich city suffering cash flow problems or a temporary income shortage.  I similarly lend them money to our mutual advantage.
2. Now, however, imagine that I am a worker who demands higher wages as the city is slowly spiraling to ruin.  Imagine that I am a banker lending for the profit of drawing interest until the debt collapses.

Well, aside from mekorot forbidding trying to destructively drain another person economically, civil law Halakha has a response to that.  Liens. This time liens against future property: 
1. Under Western capitalist arrangements in which debts are liens against property that will exist at the time of collection, Halakha would reflect the issue of responsibility.  In collecting from city assets - building, paintings, etc - an earlier contract (whether loan or employment, including retirement funds etc) takes precedence over a later contract.  

Thus, our earlier discussion of how much money to fairly give each debtor would apply only to monies left at the city's demise.

THIS DISCUSSION COULD BE NUANCED but I will stop it here.

3. Second discussion (of two) of debtor's obligation:
What about the city's residents, however?  What are they supposed to do?  True, they (or their elected officials) made bad decisions but those bad decisions were also in part due to the creditor's past demands.

Here the Halakhic discussion gets messier and more interesting.
What does ribbit mean as regards cities?
What does ribbit mean as regards cities and destructive clauses [not just interest]?
What does asmakhta mean as regards cities' contracts?
Is the argument that asmakhta is not applicable to shetarot relevant to shetarot signed by officials who don't pay the price for the commitments they made on behalf of others?  [cf. m. Bava Mezia on a father hired farmhand making a deal for himself and his minor child versus himself and his adult dependents]

Since it is late on Friday here, I will not expand these further.

4.There is only point that I would add out-of-the-box. It begins with technical info (a) and then I state the argument (b).

Technical background: 
a.  Halakha has recognized the right to bankruptcy

In Tanakh it is either every seven years (Sefer Devarim) or fifty years (Bahar).
Among Tannaim, the right was originally maintained - except as regards property that had been placed in lien (i.e. land and pawns).
Even when Halakha later allowed for permanent debts against a debtor's person, it allowed it only for purely commercial loans (such as loans in which the debtor had some assets and the documents were drawn up and deposited in the city records - prosbul [see my article]).
In other words: Loans between relatives and other people in reciprocal relationships  - loans without a shi'abud clause - were still canceled by shemitta (although a debtor who has the money is expected to repay).

This combination of rulings makes sense when we realize that the borrower and other family members/people of that circle are expected to lend to the lender in the future if he should need money.

Since the expectation is that the lender will cancel for poor family members who also have a reciprocal relationship with him, the expectation never dissapeared in Halakha:
When even oral loans became potentially permanent, the creditor had to declare publicly and in writing each specific debt that he was not foregoing [i.e. even when prosbul changed, there used to be a seperate document for each debt].  This means that there was still public pressure to forego debts from family members etc
Even when a blanket written prosbul became accepted, aharonim ruled that there is mitzva to cancel some debts [like burning some hametz] - so that there is still an expectation that a creditor will forego debts from relatives [etc]

b. What does bankruptcy based on reciprocity mean for a community?
What would that mean for a worker who lives in his town (forget a large city for the moment)?  
A town utilized the right to leave the debt: Would the ethical basis for such a right be a reciprocal relationship between the other residents and the worker?
Would a worker have a right to expect priority in being hired (cf. b. Bava Mezi'a 109a-b and rishonim through poskim)?
Would a worker have a right to expect right to tax benefits and/or a right to free use of [some] city services? [see rishonim on ha-anek ta'anik and workers versus indentured servants while keeping in mind that workers were not payed and that there is a perpetual mitzva on a debtor to pay even as he has no civil law obligation to repay after shemitta]

Shabbat shalom!

Thursday, August 8, 2013

ARTIFICIAL MEAT

Since I was asked by a former student, here are my quick thoughts on some Halakhic questions regarding the new "meat". These were merely quick thoughts. For people who have a need to think about this through a Halakhic lens - i.e. for ve-dibarta bam purposes only, not Halakhic:

Hi!

Here are quick thoughts:

1. Such meat (which was never alive) is kosher without humane slaughter (i.e. shehita).

Halakhically, even a breathing fetus calf that was removed after a cow's slaughter (ben paku'a) is minimally acceptable as food (i.e. mi-de-orraita) if it was killed in any way - although the humane cultural standard (mi-de-rabannan) is to slaughter it.

All the more so, this meat.

2. As regards the question of whether such meat must have originally come from the cells of a humanely slaughtered animal, the question is whether one relates to how this meat was originally acquired (as one might be bothered by using a human cell strain that was acquired unethically) or whether one relates to the constantly new cells as unrelated to the original meat (as one might relate to a cell strain as having no connection to an original unethical act).

Since the problematic of killing an animal inhumanely for food is not so severe (is not assur be-hana'a), the origins of the cells and thus the meat should not matter; it is no different than permitting a calf born to a mortally wounded animal because the calf is independent of the cow even as we forbid an egg (and debatably a chick) laid from a wounded hen. These new cells were not part of the dead animal.

As regards the question of whether we should have some degree of sensitivity to how these cells were acquired, there is a Tannaitic debate whether the viable calf born to a mortally wounded cow is forbidden or permitted to the altar. Does one associate the calf with the mother that either had not been protected enough against predators/the elements or had been fed sharp wounding objects negligently? The accepted position is that the calf is acceptable even as a sacrifice to G-d. All the more so as regards this "meat" in which the cells are made from cells that have been made from cells, paralleling a calf born to a calf that had been born to a mortally wounded animal; there are no triggers to recall the original animal.

Note: this argument does not permit killing an animal inhumanely (tza'ar ba'alei hayyim) in order to begin this process.

3. As regards the injunction against eating meat and milk, this new meat had no mother. Thus, the meat is no longer meat. It is all the more so not a domesticated species in spite of the fact that anything born to a species is considered part of that species no matter what it looks like. I will separate the two questions of species and of being an animal:

3a. If a calf is born with genetic mutations that make it appear more like a pig, it is still kosher calf meat. In other words, because it shares the grazing, biological and mating traits of a calf and not a pig - regardless of its appearance - it is a calf. In fact, even if it born dead, as a fetus, it is forbidden to cook and eat with milk - but that again is because it is the embryo that might have been born alive and suckled. In our case there is no emotional relationship (or even economic relationship) between cooking a killed calf/kid in the milk of a cow that is being milked until it will in turn be killed (etc etc), since this "meat" was never a developing calf. This meat is not an embryo.

3b. As regards the lesser injunction against cooking/eating milk with any meat, this "meat" does not come from an animal that was born or gestated. This meat is no different than a plant. Thus, although it has the texture of meat, the injunction does not apply.

3c. However, there is another more general - and weaker - prohibition (that is rooted in the injunction against eating milk and meat together) to consider: the prohibition against wasting protein by eating things like meat and fish together. Such haughtiness has been considered dangerous, a potential cause of leprosy, by the rabbis (and other cultures). There is in fact a modern (since 16th century) debate over whether one should also avoid eating fish with milk/cheese.

True, rich people circumvented that injunction by relating to the custom of rich Europeans to eat the fish and meat in separate courses as sufficient to not be considered gluttonous in consuming both fish and meat together. Nonetheless: I do not see room for circumvention in this case in which permitting such "meat" and milk together would also lead to people cooking and eating killed meat with dairy once the two types of meats are similar enough, cooking and eating such "meat" with milk should be forbidden. This is not a new "fence" but rather an application of the old fence that forbid cooking even chicken with almond milk without adding almonds to maintain the psychological barrier against even chicken and milk. In fact, even those who argued that almonds need not be added because the chicken is clearly not beef/goat/sheep (and the "milk" tastes completely different than real milk), would forbid mixing "meat" that (will soon) taste like meat with real milk.

Wednesday, June 26, 2013

Riding Bicycles on Shabbat - a note

In the past, when I have discussed why Ashkenazim opposed riding bicycles on Shabbat more than Middle-Eastern authorities did - I focused on the work uses of the bicycle in Europe, even between towns.  These situations obviously involved periodic fixing of flats (and fixing of the chain once that came into use).  Thus, it is not surprising that it was forbidden as the Tannaim had forbidden horse riding and that it was forbidden in language that points out how even casual riding can turn into work.

 However, I overlooked that the other grounds of opposition: bicycle riding in Europe became a group sport - which takes us back to the Ashkenazic debate over playing soccer/rugby/football on Shabbat.  It also involved inter-gender socializing, and even allowed for socializing further away from one's neighborhood of residence.  Even strangers could use their shared interest in bicycling as an opening point of conversation with the opposite gender - and all the more so a man and a woman who were strangers could meet by his offering to help fix her bicycle chain or flat.  These issues both can be found in the Halakhic language and were not as significant in Middle Eastern countries in which only men bicycled.

For some sources on Western consternation in response to bicycling (especially on the day of rest), see:

David Herlihy, Bicycle: The History. pp 266-272